Can We Trust Our Intuition? An Interview with Dr. Daniel Kahneman

EducationPeopleScienceStories

For those who employ this method, it is obviously important to find out when these case judgments are liable to error, and if they are, what, if anything, we can do to correct them.

During our walk through Covent Garden to my office at the London School of Economics, Kahneman enthusiastically recalls his meeting earlier that day with Dr. Benedetto De Martino, at the nearby Wellcome Department of Imaging Neuroscience. De Martino had studied the areas of people’s brains that become active while they are making choices. He had found that subjects who are strongly susceptible to the aforementioned gain/loss framing effects have higher activity in a part of the brain associated with emotional processing (the amygdala), whereas subjects who are less susceptible to such effects display higher activity in parts of the brain associated with analytical processing (areas in the prefrontal cortex).

The study therefore offered some support for the view that the intuitive processes that Kahneman and Tversky had uncovered operate in a distinctive part of the brain and determine judgment unless overridden by more deliberative reasoning.

Brain World: “Intuition” is a vague term. How would you define it?

Daniel Kahneman: I haven’t always been consistent in my use of the term. The first time that I used it in print, I think, was in a paper with Amos Tversky on the “Law of Small Numbers.” In that paper, we wrote something to the effect that “the Law of Large Numbers is not part of the repertoire of human intuition.” What we meant there by “intuition” was a descriptive generalization made by an objective observer about the rule that appears to generate the judgments of an individual about specific cases. And this can be an accurate description by the outside observer, even if the individual would reject this rule if he were to consider it.

I have also used the term to describe an intuitive system, a way of generating thoughts that are called intuitive thoughts. The operations of this system are typically automatic, quick, effortless, associative, and often emotionally charged. Usually, they are not open to introspection, and difficult to control or change. This intuitive system generates involuntary impressions that come to mind spontaneously, like percepts. Intuitive judgments directly reflect these impressions with little modification from the reasoning system, which functions very differently from the intuitive system.

BW: There appears to be a difference between what you call intuitive judgments, understood as a product of the intuitive system, and the type of case judgments that philosophers use to build and test their moral theories, which they also sometimes refer to as “intuitions.” Philosophers typically take these to be considered case judgments, that is, judgments that arise after reflection on the case and on our reasons for judging it as we do, whereas your category of intuitive judgments does not appear to involve such extensive reflection. What do you think of this method of arriving at considered case judgments?

DK: Well, there is a very interesting contrast between the way a psychologist would go at it and the way a philosopher would go at it, and it has a lot to do with the idea that the philosopher can know why she is reaching this conclusion. A basic assumption in psychological analysis is that you first have an intuition in a given situation. Then, when you ask yourself why you have it, you tell yourself a story. But the story you come up with does not necessarily identify the cause of your intuitions, because you typically do not have access to what causes your intuitions.

You know, many psychologists believe that consciousness is a story that we tell ourselves about ourselves. And in many cases, the story does not correspond to reality. I mean, it is very easy to create cases where you know the story isn’t true. Let me give you an example, just to push the point a little. There are experiments with posthypnotic suggestion, where you tell somebody, “I’ll clap my hands and then you’ll get up and open the window.” The person wakes up, you clap your hands, and he gets up and opens the window. If you ask him, “Why did you open the window?” he’ll say something like, “The room felt very warm.”

BW: But aren’t these cases of hypnosis simply pathological?

DK: No, they are the best examples! The beauty of these examples is that you know why the subjects are doing it. They are doing it because they were given the instruction, and then somebody clapped his hands. But they have a completely different experience of why they are doing it. What’s more, people are never at a loss for a reason why they did it. They can be made to do absolutely absurd things with posthypnotic suggestion, and yet these things seem to make sense to them when they do them. The conclusion I draw from this is that the mental operation of making sense of our intuitive judgments is a very different cognitive activity from having these intuitions.

BW: Still, the case of the hypnotic seems to show only that we cannot always trust our introspective judgments about why we act or judge as we do; it doesn’t show that we can never trust these judgments. And the method employed … others involve more than simple introspective judgment about what is driving our judgments in isolated cases. Philosophers employing this method go on to consider whether the reason they think they might be responding to in a particular case determines their judgment in other cases also.

DK: But this raises another methodological problem. There is a distinction between what I have called the “within-subject” and the “between-subject” method of considering cases. The within-subject method involves noting the intuitions a given subject has when she is considering multiple contrasting cases. The between-subject method involves noting the intuitions a subject has in a single case without engaging in explicit comparison with other cases. The two methods can elicit very different intuitions about the cases considered.

Now, because its aim is to find rules that are applicable across different cases, moral philosophy is, by its nature, restricted to the within-subject method. That is, a moral philosopher is always conscious of two or more cases and has intuitions about the differences in the two cases and about whether these differences are relevant to how she should respond. And I think this is a major limitation of moral philosophy, because, in their everyday life, people are confronted with problems one at a time, so their relevant intuitions are about cases that occur one at a time. And the moral philosopher’s stance prevents her from identifying the moral intuitions that are relevant to individuals who live their lives in this way. For this purpose, the between-subject approach, which involves asking one group of people a bout one case and another group of people about another case, is superior.

BW: That’s very interesting … I suppose I see how people’s tendency to respond differently to the same case depending on whether it is framed as involving gains or losses … would only clearly emerge in a between-subject experiment. Can you give some other examples of cases in which the two methods lead to different judgments?

DK: Let me give you two examples. First, the intuitive judgments in the grocery store cases I mentioned before, which revealed the effect of poignancy on financial compensation for the victim, could only have been elicited by the between-subject method. For if one considers the two cases side-by-side, whether the victim was at his regular grocery store or not would have appeared irrelevant, and so would have made no difference to the compensation awarded.

Second, in research I carried out with Cass Sunstein, David Schkade, and Ilana Ritov, we found that the punishments people thought appropriate when considering in isolation cases of business fraud differed significantly from punishments they thought appropriate when they compared cases of business fraud with wrongdoing involving bodily injury. Our hypothesis was that outrage at an act was a significant contributor to the size of the punishment people judged appropriate. When they considered a case of business fraud in isolation, people implicitly compared the case to other cases of business fraud, so their level of outrage was determined by how egregious the conduct was as compared to other cases of business fraud. A particularly egregious case of business fraud would therefore be very heavily punished.

However, in comparing cases of business fraud with cases of a different category altogether, like bodily injury, the relative importance of the category to which the wrongdoing belongs became relevant as well. Since bodily injury was regarded as generally worse than fraud, this could make the same case of fraud seem less worthy of severe punishment.

You May Also Like

5 Steps to Banish Disease From Your Mind
The Quest for an Alzheimer’s Cure: An Interview with Dr. Paul Coleman

Sponsored Link

About Us

A magazine dedicated to the brain.

We believe that neuroscience is the next great scientific frontier, and that advances in understanding the nature of the brain, consciousness, behavior, and health will transform human life in this century.

Education and Training

Newsletter Signup

Subscribe to our newsletter below and never miss the news.

Stay Connected

Pinterest